• The Aesthetics of Horror and Disgust – Justin Lieberman

    Date posted: April 30, 2006 Author: jolanta

    The Aesthetics of Horror and Disgust

    Justin Lieberman

    The method of art
    making in which the interpretation of the work is entirely determined by the
    artist is a relatively new concept. This particular approach may be seen as one
    that directly opposes modernism. As meaning ceases to become ambiguous, the idea
    of a center (god, science, universality of experience) is driven from the work.
    In the past, a work’s ambiguity has often been seen as strength. For 2 reasons:

    1.In modernism,
    this ambiguity was said to have lent the work Autonomy. By not relying on an
    existing pre-ordained set of signs in order to make a statement (in the sense
    that language does) the work separates itself from and declares itself independent
    of the existing world.

    2.In post-modernism,
    ambiguity is sometimes seen as a metaphor for the lack of certainty as to the
    truth of commonly agreed upon meanings attributed to signs or symbols.

    Modernism’s reliance on the presumption of the universality of all human
    experience in certain absolutes is a reliance contingent on faith. Such a method
    of art making can never dwell in the concrete reality that is the world. Post-modernism’s
    assumption that communication is impossible fails to recognize the reality of
    the discourse through which we understand ideas as they are presented to us.

    Both of these ideas
    are reliant on a belief system of art’s role in society as a purveyor of
    mystic truths. These truths may be metaphysical, social, and cultural.

    Both bastardize the clarity of their message through the meaningless valorization
    of ambiguity.

    If, as Bataille
    proposes, the two dominant modes of human interaction are indeed appropriation
    and excretion, (1) then artists in order to communicate or represent the world
    in which they live must acknowledge this and act accordingly. The artist who
    presumes to create original artworks is doomed to a series of mute, incommunicative
    gesticulations, like one who has suddenly lost his voice. These are the gesticulations
    of the artist who attempts to communicate broad universal truths. The viewer
    recognizes this attempt and unconsciously substitutes his own ideas for the ones
    the artist has intended. Two deaf old women conversing with each other make all
    the gestures, little nods of understanding, pauses in speech, and signs of recognition
    that people who understand one another do, but it is merely the hollow shell
    of a conversation that they are carrying out.

    A work of art may
    fix its interpretation and thus attain clarity by utilizing signs as they have
    come to be understood by a particular audience w/o altering their meaning. Then
    re-presenting these signs to said audience in combination. Taking signs whole
    and unaltered into a work is appropriation. The re-presentation of these signs
    is excretion.

    In the 1960’s the group of artists known as the Vienna Actionists executed
    a series of performances that carried the idea of transgression in art to extremes,
    which had yet to be even hinted at, by art that preceded them. The artists Gunter
    Brus, Hermann Nitsch, Rudolf Schwarzkogler, and Otto Muhl used blood, self-painting,
    animal sacrifice, self-mutilation, and sex in an iconoclastic and self-destructive
    way that was often ironic and humorous (particularly in the cases of Brus and
    Muhl) rather than spiritual in its associations. The extremity of their transgressions
    have made subsequent attempts at transgression in an art context seem pithy by
    comparison. For the contemporary artist, the creation of work that relies on
    physical or sexual violence for its transgression is no longer viable, as these
    are everywhere in our culture and have ceased to constitute a transgression at
    all.

    After the death of art, (was it ever alive?) what options are open to the artist
    that he may continue his practice? I suggest the one-liner as a possible solution
    to this problem. The one-liner makes use of both appropriation and excretion
    simultaneously as it evades the essentialism inherent in the grand idea. In its
    combination of appropriated elements, the one-liner functions as a stepladder
    to it’s own implications, which can be manifold. Each person’s reaction
    reveals something of both the joke and themselves. So, in the same way that a
    joke provokes different reactions based on the context in which it is told, so
    does the artwork whose interpretation is fixed reflect back each viewer’s
    particular perception of it. In this way the object asserts itself and may stand
    in judgment even as it is being judged. However, there is a problem with this
    game-like system of art-making and art criticism in which the shuffling of variables
    is of primary concern.

    Herbert Read, in
    his essay ‘Psycho-analysis and the problem of aesthetic value’ (2)
    attacks the Freudian psychoanalytic view of art as reductive, placing too much
    importance on the subject of a work of art and not enough on its formal qualities,
    which he sees as art’s primary concern. In a way, this is true insomuch
    as an art with no formal qualities would be little more than a game itself, a
    useless diversion. Art must bear some relationship to real lived everyday experience.
    But how? The experience of art calls into question any notion of the real to
    begin with. In our suspension of disbelief before a work of art, what had once
    seemed concrete reality begins to crumble. Bataille says of poetry: “…starting
    from the moment when this unreality immediately constitutes itself as a superior
    reality, whose mission is to eliminate (or degrade) inferior vulgar reality,
    poetry is reduced to playing the standard role of things…”(3)

    I believe there is yet another solution to the problem of ambiguous meaning,
    and this is to expand our definition of art to include objects which have no
    meaning at all. Specifically, objects that were not created with the intention
    of becoming works of art.

    Art that serves
    a purpose, i.e.; is not useless, renounces its status as art and becomes merely
    applied art. (4) Although it does not necessarily follow that all useless things
    are art, I believe that the intention to create a real thing and its subsequent
    failure could also constitute a work of art. I refer to a real thing in the sense
    that art and real things are often identical in appearance. (5) Heidigger referred
    to these failed pieces of equipment as present-at-hand, meaning that they made
    themselves ostentatious through the frustration experienced at their attempted
    use. (6) Heidigger found this ostentatious-ness to be bland and boring, but is
    art so different? The object in question would possess a number of interesting
    qualities. In some ways it would resemble a kitsch object by carrying with it
    the history of it’s own debasement. But it would also be linked to the performative
    in that this would be a compressed physical history of debasement rather than
    a cultural one. It differs from the readymade in that it is not a functioning
    real thing made useless by its declared status as art. More likely it was made
    useless by poor design or craftsmanship. Whereas the readymade could be put back
    into use with little effort, the new type of object is dead to the old world
    of useful things and may only go on living in its artificial zombie-like state
    as a work of art. It differs from a camp object in that it is not a failed work
    of art. It possesses no such glamour. As a failed real thing it is difficult
    to surpass in its banality which is beyond intention. Broken machines and crumbling
    architecture are like blind spots in our vision. Memory glosses over them as
    if they weren’t there. Because of their invisibility, they are the haunt
    of crime and this makes their banality ominous. The laughter that accompanies
    the failed real thing is a cold and heartless one.

     

    ************************************************************

    1.Bataille, Georges. “The Use Value of D.A.F. de Sade (An Open Letter to
    my Current Comrades) (1929-30)”, in Allan Stoekl (Ed.), Bataille, Georges.
    Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927-1939, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
    Press

    2.Read, Herbert. (1950), “Psycho-analysis and the Problem of Aesthetic Value”.
    The Forms of Things Unknown: Essays Toward an Aesthetic Philosophy. New York:
    Faber and Faber, pg. 76-93.

    3.Bataille, Georges. “The Use Value of D.A.F. de Sade (An Open Letter to
    my Current Comrades) (1929-30)”, in Allan Stoekl (Ed.), Bataille, Georges.
    Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927-1939, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
    Press, pg.97

    4.Richter, Gerhard. “Notes, 1988”. The Daily Practice of Painting:
    Writings 1962-1993. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, pg.170 Here, Richter
    is referring specifically to art objects that function in a practical way, be
    it socially, politically or even culturally. Graphic Design for example.

    5.Danto, Arthur. “Works of Art and Mere Real Things”. The Transfiguration
    of The Commonplace: A Philosophy of Art. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
    Press, pg.3

    6.Heidigger, Martin. The Origin of the Work of Art

    Comments are closed.